Why I am Skeptical of Market Failure Corrections

In just about any economics textbook, one will find a discussion of market failure.  The conversation will usually go something like this: markets are great, but sometimes they fail.  If transaction costs are low, then no government remedy is needed.  But if transaction costs are high, then the government can (and should) step in to correct the failure.  One of the most common methods advocated to correct a market failure is the original from British economist Arthur C. Pigou: taxes.

A Pigouvian tax is a tax designed to fix a specific market failure: negative externalities.  A negative externality is a situation where costs are imposed on a 3rd party outside of the transaction.  Since they are not part of the original transaction, the monetary price that occurs in the market does not fully take into account their costs.  Thus, a tax can be applied that raises the market price, reduces the quantity in the market, compensates for the costs imposed, and the market failure is removed.  Negative externalities seem to be pervasive in society (pollution, bad smells, second-hand smoke, etc).  Furthermore, transaction costs are high (imagine if a power plant had to negotiate with every person who is affected by its smog!).  Consequently, you have many economists taking the need for Pigouvian taxes as a given.

I, however, am very much in a minority.  While I understand the logic behind Pigouvian taxes, I reject them as a practical solution; I do not think they are a 1st-best, or even 12th-best solution to market failure.  Public Choice economics gives us a major reason to be skeptical of government-imposed market failures, even so-called “market-based” interventions like Pigouvian taxes or cap-and-trade.  The assumption behind Pigouvian taxes (or any government intervention in the economy) is that the government is a benevolent dictator; it seeks to do the right thing and can do so unilaterally.  But Public Choice teaches us that we must consider the world as it actually is as opposed to some idealized alternative state.

In the real world, the government is neither benevolent nor a dictatorship.  Government agents are not benevolent, but neither are they generally malevolent.  They, like all of us, are looking out for their own best interests.  They want to keep their jobs, they want to do a good job, they want to go home to their families at the end of the day, etc.  They have hopes, dreams, and desires.  And they act in line with their incentives and their goals, which probably differ from most other people.  What incentive, then, is there for them to assign “the proper” tax to solve an externality, or even to gather all necessary information to properly assign it?

In the real world, the government (at least in the United States) is not a dictatorship.  It has many working parts.  Many policy decisions are made in committees, or determined by Congressional vote.  Policy-makers and decision-makers are balancing many, many different issues.  Consequently, policy more often than not deviates from a theoretical ideal and hedges more toward being politically correct. (By that I mean: the policy is correct for some political goal rather than some non-political goal.)  

In a recent post, Pierre Lemieux highlights one such case of politically-correct policy: tariffs on Chinese-made electric vehicles (EVs).  We are often told that global warming is a significant issue and one that warrants significant government involvement.  Indeed, it is the justification for many government subsidies to green energy (a reverse Pigouvian tax) and a carbon tax.  From that perspective, the tariffs on Chinese-made EVs make no sense.  If there is a negative externality, and there is a product on the market that can reduce the externality, then why effectively prohibit it?  The answer: because those cars were not politically correct.  They solved the market failure, but not in the politically desired way.  Thus, the administration, looking to protect its voter base and accomplish its own goals of staying elected, opted to take an action that makes the externality worse rather than better.  All in the name of stopping the externality.  

Why do I oppose a carbon tax?  Because I see no reason why it also will not become subject to such political correctness.  Even if it were possible to accurately and costlessly calculate the necessary tax, why should we believe it would not be implemented and designed in such a way as to favor certain groups and achieve political goals rather than economic?  

 


Jon Murphy is an assistant professor of economics at Nicholls State University.

READER COMMENTS

Bill
Jul 17 2024 at 11:12am

Nicely argued.

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 11:19am

Thank you!

David Seltzer
Jul 17 2024 at 1:33pm

Ditto!

Craig
Jul 17 2024 at 12:24pm

A pet peeve I have is when Pigovian taxes are spoken of in the context of funding something on an ongoing basis.

vince
Jul 17 2024 at 1:42pm

 

… they act in line with their incentives

 

Getting incentives right, across the board, would solve most problems.  For example it would have avoided the GFC.  But who gets to determine the incentive structure?  The devil is in the details.  Suddenly, it’s back to politics.

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 2:56pm

Getting incentives right, across the board, would solve most problems.

Indeed.  Though, as was pointed out way back in 1775 by Adam Smith (and confirmed by research through the modern day), that is not a tractable problem at the economy-wide level.  Indeed, even at the individual level, getting incentives right is extraordinarily difficult.

For that reason, I reject your argument “Suddenly, it’s back to politics.”  Not everything needs to be politics.  Indeed, as has been reconogized by liberals for centuries now, the realm of politics should be very very small compared to the realm of the personal.  To have one spill into the other, to apply the rules of one to the rules of the other, is to destory the very order one wishes to create (see FA Hayek on this point in The Fatal Conceit).  

Politics should remain in its proper realm.  When it expands into social, economic, personal, and cultural areas, it crushes them for the very reason you cite.

vince
Jul 17 2024 at 3:20pm

 

Politics should remain in its proper realm.

 

Easier said than done.  Who keeps it there?  Who even decides what that realm is?  That’s politics.

Dylan
Jul 17 2024 at 1:45pm

Agreed this was a nice piece, Jon, and I agree with everything you wrote. Pigovian taxes I think will suffer from all of the issues you flagged. However, I think they are still better than the next most likely alternative, which isn’t doing nothing, it is doing contradictory things like subsidizing demand on one side and restricting supply on the other.

The goal in advocating for carbon taxes isn’t to get to some ideal where the tax perfectly matches the subsidy, it is to move the Overton window in a direction so that command and control regulations are off the table. We seemed to be moving in that direction throughout much of the 90s and 2000s, so we know it is possible to have market based interventions as the preferred solution…but we’ve backslid a lot since then and now hardly any politician even tries to make that case and instead go for maximally interventionist and inefficient policies that can be counterproductive to the goal, like the EV tariffs in your example.

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 2:13pm

You’re not really stating an alternative, though. You’re just describing what I’m talking about: the justification gets twisted to serve a political end rather than an optimizing end.

Dylan
Jul 17 2024 at 2:52pm

Let me try in a different way. Let’s say, for simplicity sake that there are 3 ways to try and deal with an externality 1) Do nothing, 2) Pigovian taxes/cap and trade/other “market based” solutions, 3) Command and control or other less efficient methods

My proposition is, the natural state of affairs in for government to do 3. I think with a lot of work outlining the benefits of market based solutions, by economists, journalists, and others…we can increase the public appetite for 2 and get to a Pareto improvement.

I think of it similarly to free trade, there are a lot of incentives at work for politicians pushing against free trade, and yet we moved in a more and more free trade direction for a long time, even if it wasn’t perfect and their were carve outs and red tape and all the rest, it was still an improvement over what came before. I suspect you advocate for more free trade policies, even given Public Choice realities?

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 2:57pm

I think we were typing at the same time (see my comment below).  I had misread your comment as I was eating lunch

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 2:47pm

Actually, I wish to retract my comment.  I see what you’re saying now that I’ve thought about your comment some more.  Yes, compared to interventions that do positive harm, a “politically correct” intervention could be better.

But the alternative I’m posing is no intervention whatsoever.

Dylan
Jul 17 2024 at 2:58pm

Yeah, I understood your preference would be for choice 1 (in my list from my above comment). I think the political forces you outline make that not a realistic option much of the time and if you argue for 1 you will get 3. I’d personally prefer for people in your position to argue for 1 and why, but also state clearly that 2 is far preferable to 3.  My goal is to make 3 politically infeasible.

 

nobody.really
Jul 17 2024 at 3:52pm

I struggle with this argument.

Yes, the choice to implement a policy will be driven by political (self-interested) considerations. But as Jon Murphy et al. observe, the choice to refrain from adopting a Pagouvian tax is itself a policy–just as prone to being the result of politicial/self-interested considerations. Indeed, because inaction is the easiest policy to implement, I suspect that inaction is adopted more often than is justified by other considerations.

In sum, I find Murphy’s argument persuasive AND ultimately irrelevant.

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 4:36pm

I guess I don’t see how it is irrelevant.  Pigouvian taxes (and market failure policies in general):

-Are major planks in the platforms of both major US political parties

-Are staples in any undergraduate economics textbook

-Have been implimented in several US states and several other countries

Even if, ultimately, there is a tendency to do nothing (a claim that is not likely true), I think analyzing policies that are actively being discussed is relevant.

nobody.really
Jul 17 2024 at 5:06pm

The topic is … well, topical. But your argument–that we can’t trust any policy decision because it may be burdened by self-interested actors–applies equally to doing anything, including DOING NOTHING. So it’s like adding an equal weight to both sides of a scale: ultimately, the scale doesn’t move.

If you choose not to decide, you still have made a choice.

Neil Peart, “Freewill,” Rush’s Permanant Waves (1980)

nobody.really
Jul 17 2024 at 5:26pm

(Having just quoted Freewill, I’ll note that this discussion reminds me of arguments against free will: It doesn’t matter how good the arguments for determinism are, I could never choose to believe them—because if determinism obtained, I could never choose … anything. So in a 2×2 matrix (Does determinism obtain: y/n; Do I believe in determinism: y/n), I see no advantage to choosing to believe in it. If determinism obtains, then I have no choice; I will believe whatever the causal forces lead me to believe. The only circumstance under which I could make a choice would be a circumstance without determinism. And under that circumstance, the accurate choice seems obvious.)

Jon Murphy
Jul 17 2024 at 5:45pm

that we can’t trust any policy decision because it may be burdened by self-interested actors–applies equally to doing anything,

Well, then the problem is solved. That’s not my argument.

MarkW
Jul 17 2024 at 3:26pm

Why should we believe it would not be implemented and designed in such a way as to favor certain groups and achieve political goals rather than economic?  

It wouldn’t.  Or, if by some miracle, it is was so designed, such a law would not be approved  or would not be long preserved in its original politically neutral form.  A real-world case in point was the attempt to impose a revenue-neutral carbon tax in Washington State..  In the main, it failed because it was opposed by activists on the left.  And why?  You can probably guess why:

Given how difficult it is to raise revenue in the state, the idea, often put forward by I-732 proponents, that greens can simply find that money somewhere else is, in the alliance’s view, naive to the point of malice. Labor groups want investments to incentivize green manufacturing and retrain displaced workers. Communities of color and low-income groups want “a share of the money to go to the infrastructure that we need to weather climate change,” says Schaefer, like affordable housing near public transit. Tax cuts and credits “are not going help the folks I work with go out and buy a [Nissan] Leaf,” Schaefer says.

 

David Seltzer
Jul 17 2024 at 3:31pm

Jon: Good stuff. I too am skeptical of a carbon tax to resolve the issue of emissions. In terms of just compensation for those harmed outside of the market mechanism; different individuals are impacted more or less severely How does a carbon tax differentiate? A healthy person may be less affected than someone with asthma or emphysema. A one time class action suit settlement is preferred to ongoing taxes which will be raised over time. The incentive for the carbon producer, at the margin, would be to internalize the externality. Inland Steel in East Chicago, installed effluent scrubbers in the early 1970’s. Some would suggest a Coasian negotiation and compensation. I suspect  Coasian solutions are more effective for small, localized externalities than for larger global externalities unless there are effective societal sanctions.

Scott Sumner
Jul 17 2024 at 6:49pm

I would prefer a tax on activities that produce external costs over a tax on activities that produce external benefits.

nobody.really
Jul 18 2024 at 7:44pm

Excellent thought. As I understand it, Jon Murphy opposes Pigouvian taxes because they are, or will become, in some sense suboptimal. But how suboptimal would they need to become before they would become a worse mechanism for public finance than the current income tax?

Jon Murphy
Jul 19 2024 at 6:25am

But how suboptimal would they need to become before they would become a worse mechanism for public finance than the current income tax?

They’d instantly be such. A pigouvian tax is not meant to be a source of revenue.

nobody.really
Jul 19 2024 at 9:32am

Now I’m really baffled. It’s a tax, yes? What happens to the resulting revenues?

Jon Murphy
Jul 19 2024 at 9:49am

The pigouvian tax does raise some revenue, but that’s not its goal. The amount it raises is relatively small (in theory, none as all the revenue should be used to offset the dead weight loss from the externality).

Thus a Pigouvian tax would be too large if it’s raising revenue (especially at the scale of an income tax) and would instantly be suboptimal. It’s not a revenue tax.

By way of metaphor, a hammer is a suboptimal way to screw in a screw even though both hammers and screwdrivers are screwdrivers

Jon Murphy
Jul 19 2024 at 9:52am

Sorry that last sentence should read “hammers are screwdrivers are both tools”

nobody.really
Jul 19 2024 at 12:19pm

Thus a Pigouvian tax would be too large if it’s raising revenue (especially at the scale of an income tax) and would instantly be suboptimal. It’s not a revenue tax.

As far as I can tell, every dollar raised by a Pigouvian tax is one less dollar to be raised by some other tax. And surely those other taxes generate deadweight losses, too?

The amount it raises is relatively small (in theory, none as all the revenue should be used to offset the dead weight loss from the externality).

Very well. How would YOU propose to offset the deadweight loss from an externality in the absence of a Pigouvian tax? If you’d use an income tax, then you must concede that the two forms of taxation are substitutes. Or are you saying that you prefer a world in which people burdened by externalities go uncompensated? In that case, the revenues from the Pigouvian tax would be available as general revenue, again acting as a substitute for other forms of taxation.

I surmise you would argue that, indeed, you prefer a world without a Pigouvian tax, even if this results in people going uncompensated, because you think the mischief to be caused by the tax would be greater than its benefit. I surmise you would make an equal-protection type argument: Income taxes are rife with special-interest provisions, but the net effect of these abuses is to spread burdens broadly. Pigouvian taxes will also be subject to abusive control, but the net effect will be to focus the burdens of these abuses narrowly.

For example, it’s not crazy to think that smokers impose additional cost on public health programs, and thus government might strive to recover some of the cost of these programs via a tax on cigarettes. But beyond a certain point, this Pigouvian tax just becomes a tax on a politically powerless minority. The only way to defend politically powerless minorities is by insisting on equal protection of the laws–which, in this case, means rejecting Pigouvian taxes in general.

The longer I think about it, the less crazy it sounds….

steve
Jul 17 2024 at 9:07pm

This is just a slippery slope argument. Following your logic you should never get out of bed in the morning because something bad might happen.

Steve

Don Boudreaux
Jul 18 2024 at 6:12am

Steve: It’s not a slippery-slope argument. Jon’s argument rests on the distinction between market activity and political activity, with the first being far better than the latter at gathering and processing the relevant knowledge that must be used to improve states of the world, and then acting on that knowledge in ways not distorted by political biases. To reject Pigouvian taxation is not to say “Ok, we must do nothing. Just stay in bed.” Instead, it’s to allow greater scope to market activities, where lots of things will, in fact, be done.

The government is not us; “we” are not synonymous with the state.

Dylan
Jul 18 2024 at 7:22am

But that’s just it, Pigouvian taxes are what allows for greater scope of market activities. Yes, there is an entity that is setting the ultimate goal, and that process is likely to get hijacked by the political process and not be what a theoretically ideal tax would be. But, even an imperfect tax on a big enough externality is likely to be better than nothing, and certainly better than the hodge podge of giveaways to special interests that is what the political process typically delivers.

Don Boudreaux
Jul 18 2024 at 7:53am

Dylan: You implicitly assume that Pigouvian interventions will make matters better – that they will move the privately experienced marginal costs and benefits closer to the ‘social’ marginal costs and benefits. I see no reason to suppose that, in general, the government is likely to make matters better with Pigouvian interventions. It has no access to the necessary knowledge, and it’s a political, not an economic, engine.

Dylan
Jul 18 2024 at 3:49pm

You implicitly assume that Pigouvian interventions will make matters better – that they will move the privately experienced marginal costs and benefits closer to the ‘social’ marginal costs and benefits.

I explicitly assume this. But my base case comparison isn’t against doing nothing, it is against the status quo of policies that actively do the opposite of what they supposedly intend to do.

Take for an example a policy proposal currently getting a lot of support in NYC, banning apartment broker fees because the rent is too darn high. I’m guessing you won’t have a problem seeing how that policy won’t lower housing costs for people and is quite likely to do the opposite?

That’s the kind of thing that often takes the place of pigouvian taxes. By arguing against them, you are implicitly arguing for mandatory fuel economy standards, ethanol subsidies, EV tax credits, the exact type of carbon capture technology that power generators must use, etc.

Jon Murphy
Jul 18 2024 at 6:46am

What Don said. My argument is not “some risk exists, therefore do nothing.” Rather, it’s to compare various alternatives, risks and all.

Thomas L Hutcheson
Jul 18 2024 at 7:21am

“compare various alternatives, risks and all” is classic welfare economics.  Sometimes the status quo works as the alternative policy, but sometimes not.

For climate change policy, I think the status quo quite bad.  We are already incurring very high costs to reduce net CO2 emissions.  For all I know the current panoply of subsidies to alternative technologies and mandates are already greater than the deadweight loss of a tax on net emissions (as likely to come out of the sausage-making machine).

Analytically, I think it makes sense to separate estimating the costs of the ideal policy from estimating the costs of the Public Choice (or other) departures from the ideal.  Unfortunately, the latter is not nearly so well developed as the former.

Jon Murphy
Jul 18 2024 at 8:48am

Unfortunately, the latter is not nearly so well developed as the former.

Given the tremendous amount of research and estimates done over the past century, I feel like that claim is indefensible.

Thomas L Hutcheson
Jul 17 2024 at 11:23pm

You have used Public Choice theory to calculate the expected costs and benefit of a tax on net emissions of CO2.  This seems perfectly consistent with conventional welfare economics.  Public Choice Theory should be used at every stage — advocacy, legislation, execution.

Jon Murphy
Jul 18 2024 at 9:16am

This seems perfectly consistent with conventional welfare economics.

Indeed. The problem with conventional welfare economics as currently taught and practiced is it assumes away public choice and comparative economic concerns.

Knut P. Heen
Jul 18 2024 at 7:55am

People tend to forget that the value of a good is subjective when they start talking about externalities. Here is an example with asymmetric information.

Your neighbor is playing the violin. You can hear him playing. Is this a positive or negative externality? It depends on whether you think it is music or noise, but how would a bureaucrat know whether to tax you and subsidize your neighbor, or subsidize you and tax your neighbor? Pigou does not consider asymmetric information.

The market solution is simple. If you think it is music, you pay your neighbor to play more. If it is noise, you pay him to stop playing when you are at home.

 

David Seltzer
Jul 18 2024 at 10:24am

Nice example.

nobody.really
Jul 18 2024 at 5:31pm

The market solution is simple. If you think it is music, you pay your neighbor to play more. If it is noise, you pay him to stop playing when you are at home.

1: He currently plays one hour every Saturday at 7pm. You tell him you’re willing to pay him $10 to stop playing then. He demands $1 million, or no deal. You decline to pay $1 million, so he keeps playing. How is this a remedy?

2: Moreover, now the neighbor begins playing morning, noon, and night in order to increase your incentive to deal. Great solution.

So you cut a deal with him. Now all the other neighbors being playing ear-splitting rock & roll in order to extort money from you. And they begin setting fires in their BBQ pits to flood your yard with smoke. And they store lots of brush in their yards; vermin live in the brush and begin infesting your yard. And they begin excavating right up to your property line, creating a risk that your land will crumble. And they build giant skyscraper next door that blocks all your sunlight. Or they’d have sex in the back yard in front of your kids. Etc., etc.

As long as English common law has recognized property rights, it has recognized the concept of NUISIANCE–a condition, activity, or situation that interferes with the use or enjoyment of property in an unreasonable and substantial way. “Interfere,” “unreasonable,” and “substantial” are all culturally derived judgments. In various regions of the world, at various times, courts have reached different conclusions about what constitutes a nuisance. Nuisance laws (and their successors–zoning and homeowner association laws) are what would enable you to avoid being extorted forever.

3: For what it’s worth, has ANYONE ever actually implemented the policy Knut P. Heen proposed? For example, for most of my life people smoked. Lots of people didn’t like this practice, but I cannot ever recall observing a scenario when someone negotiated a price to get someone else to refrain from smoking.

In the case of the violin, I cannot quite imagine how this conversation would go. Where I live, people have norms about autonomy–and an offer to pay someone to stop playing the violin would come across as 1) nosy, 2) judgy, 3) controlling, 4) offensive, and 5) demeaning.

It would be awkward enough to simply ask a neighbor to refrain from playing or smoking. But proposing to create a payor/payee, principle/subordinate relationship would really be beyond the pale. I guess these kinds of negotiations might seem entirely reasonable to libertarians working on a Homo Economus model, but seem to strike actual human beings as intrusive/awkward/burdensome to negotiate.

But maybe that’s just me. This is a reasonally well-read blog. Can anyone here attest to having negotiated this kind of relationship with a neighbor? Ever?

Jon Murphy
Jul 20 2024 at 11:03am

3: For what it’s worth, has ANYONE ever actually implemented the policy Knut P. Heen proposed? For example, for most of my life people smoked. Lots of people didn’t like this practice, but I cannot ever recall observing a scenario when someone negotiated a price to get someone else to refrain from smoking.

These sorts of bargains happen all the time.  Indeed, English Common Law is full of such examples.  Elinor Ostrom won the Nobel Prize in exploring different ways agreements form.

How is this a remedy?

It shows the person playing values the music more than the person hearing it prefers the quiet.  There is no relevant externality in this case (and note that imposing restrictions on the violin player results in a suboptimal solution).

nobody.really
Jul 20 2024 at 11:56pm

These sorts of bargains happen all the time. Indeed, English Common Law is full of such examples. Elinor Ostrom won the Nobel Prize in exploring different ways agreements form.

Delighted to hear it. Odd that not a single commentor on this blog could cite an example of engaging in such a transaction.

 

In any event, could you give us some real-world examples of such negotiations, so that we might assess how similar they are to this hypothetical question?

There is no relevant externality in this case….

Imagine people were perpetually stealing your tools and trespassing across your lawn. If they refused every offer you made to get them to stop, would you therefore conclude that there was no “relevant externality” to yourself?

[N]ote that imposing restrictions on the violin player results in a suboptimal solution….

I propose that the landowner in question could bring a nuisance action against the violin player. If successful, this finding would NOT prohibit the violin player from playing; it would merely require the violin player to compensate the landowner for his inconvenience. Why would that be a suboptimal solution?

Of course, this is no magic solution either. The landowner could then demand any price he liked, even a price that exceeded the minimum he would accept–much like the violin player had before. The consequence of the nuisance suit would merely change which party had the power to engage in holdout behavior–a fact that would very likely influence the outcome of the subsequent negotiations.

In short, I find nothing especially meritorious about either outcome. The choice to award property rights in the discretion to play the violin, or to live in the peace of not having to hear the neighbor’s violin, strikes me as arbitrary–yet consequential to the parties involved. The mere fact that property rights may be difficult to enforce does not mean that transgression of those rights fails to create an externality.

Pierre Lemieux
Jul 26 2024 at 5:26pm

Nobody: I think you will agree that numerous parts of your comment can be enlightened by some economic analysis (that is, the analysis of how spontaneous orders work efficiently). Let me mention a few points:

But maybe that’s just me. This is a reasonally well-read blog. Can anyone here attest to having negotiated this kind of relationship with a neighbor? Ever?

Probably nobody has tried buying or selling, for the same price as the packages offered on the market, cars disassembled in 1,000 pieces, or negotiating with his future wife (or husband) a price for sex by the act, and so forth. Lots of things come as package deals, if only because of transaction costs. In fact, every good or service, except the simplest ones, is a package deal. (You can however get a Bughati almost built by hand, for 10 times the price of a ready-made car.) Same for neighborhoods and relations with neighbors. If the sort of neighborhood you describe exists, the price of a house must be very low to compensate the buyer for the troubles you describe (like when buying a floodable lot).

As long as English common law has recognized property rights, it has recognized the concept of NUISIANCE.

Yes, and this is well known by economists at least since Ronald Coase’s famous 1960 article “The Problem of Social Cost.” There is much to discover in this article. Anthony de Jasay reminds us of the difference between a nuisance and an “insignificant externality.”

I cannot ever recall observing a scenario when someone negotiated a price to get someone else to refrain from smoking.

This is not how externalities are usually solved, by piecemeal bargaining. Indeed, on very competitive markets, there is no bargaining at all. Before governments started prohibiting restaurant owners from welcoming smokers, there were some non-smoking restaurants (I think vegetarian restaurants were usually among them). If there had been a market for more, private entrepreneurs would have been incentivized entrepreneurs to open more. (Greed works miracles, but not in the way of the neighborhood you describe.) Remember my point on private property as a device to solve conflicts. Since most customers were apparently not willing to pay for more non-smoking restaurants, contrary to what politically-correct anti-smoking (often government-subsidized) activists wanted, the latter obtained from government the prohibition of all smoking restaurants.

John
Jul 18 2024 at 10:13am

Market failure is a legal fiction.

Negative externalities result from the collectivization of property, and can be eliminated via innovative markets and proportionalization, localization, and individualization.

Any problem creates a demand for its solution in proportion to the cost.

Bureaucratic “solutions” create their own set of problems, rely on compulsion, and create incentives for corruption.

The internalization of externalities simply requires the accountability of the tortfeasors (i.e. polluters) to their victims (those who have suffered losses or damages) along with those who assist them in righting said wrongs, and in direct proportion to said wrongs.

Such an approach would also incentivize and broaden the market for pollution prevention.

Jon Murphy
Jul 19 2024 at 6:33am

Market failure is a legal fiction.

No. Market failure is not a legal term. It’s a condition: either the market is below some optimal level (as defined by welfare economics) or participants have failed to achieve their goal(s) (as originally defined). It’s a condition that does exist (and I argue is vital to the market functioning).

Negative externalities result from the collectivization of property

Again, no. Negative externalities exist because people exist in proximity to one another. Collectivization of property may lead to more externalities (tragedy of the commons), but externalities are a common fact of life.

I generally agree with the rest of your comment, but I wanted to correct those two issues.

Pierre Lemieux
Jul 26 2024 at 4:33pm

Good post, Jon–and it shows from the comments it has generated. I would have cited it in my Generator post if I had seen it in time.

Comments are closed.

RECENT POST

In a previous post, I argued that more than 100% of the inflation since late 2019 has been demand side. There were some adverse supply shocks around 2021-22 that led to significant inflation, but there have also been major positive supply shocks (notably immigration) that have tended to depress inflation. In net terms,...

Read More

International trade, it is commonly said, has winners and losers. Consumers in the U.S. gain when they buy wine imported from France while winemakers in California lose. C’est la vie, counsel economists. Nothing should be done about this situation. The reason is that it’s also commonly said – at least among those...

Read More

In just about any economics textbook, one will find a discussion of market failure.  The conversation will usually go something like this: markets are great, but sometimes they fail.  If transaction costs are low, then no government remedy is needed.  But if transaction costs are high, then the government can (and s...

Read More