
James M. Buchanan was an economist known for his affiliation with the “Virginia School of Political Economy,” otherwise known as Public Choice theory. Trained at the University of Chicago, his academic journey led him to teach at the University of Virginia, Virginia Tech, and George Mason University. Buchanan’s contributions to public choice theory, which extends economic analysis to political domains, earned him the Nobel Prize in economics in 1986.

Although Public Choice theory maintains a somewhat subdued presence in mainstream economics, Buchanan’s theories are held in disproportionately high regard within libertarian circles. This can be attributed to the fact that public choice theory takes a more realistic view of government benevolence than does mainstream economics. Just as important, however, Buchanan was one of the last libertarians to receive the highest honor in the field of economics, propelling him to a place of elevated status.
Despite Buchanan being a prolific writer and a meticulous scholar, his ideas are leading libertarians astray in some areas and may help explain the lack of progress in Austrian economics in recent decades. There are at least three aspects of Buchanan’s work that deserve closer scrutiny.
Buchanan’s Perspective on Cost: In the 1960s, Buchanan authored a brief text titled “Cost and Choice: An Inquiry in Economic Theory.” The organization and writing of this work resemble more a set of disordered musings than a structured publication. Nevertheless, the book has been highly influential among libertarians. One could encapsulate its core message in the single phrase: “cost is subjective.” Buchanan at times characterized himself as a “radical subjectivist.” Despite Buchanan’s somewhat nuanced stance in the book, his disciples have often interpreted his writings to mean that costs are a psychological phenomenon and “not measurable in monetary terms.” This leads to the ironic situation whereby libertarians misunderstand the idea of opportunity cost and overlook the substantial opportunity costs that governments inflict daily through their inefficient policies. Costs, by their nature, are objective and quantifiable magnitudes in the real world, even if psychological factors shape the market prices used to measure them.
Buchanan’s Views on Social Welfare Functions: In the mid-20th century, economists were searching for a coherent way to measure human welfare. They seemed to be making progress when Kenneth Arrow published a groundbreaking paper in which he proved that no social welfare measure can be formed from the preferences of the members of a community, which also satisfies certain criteria of “reasonableness.” Buchanan correctly criticized Arrow for this “impossibility” theorem. However, his criticism was based largely on the grounds that social outcomes shouldn’t be expected to adhere to a notion of individual rationality. In a twist of irony, Buchanan’s stance probably inadvertently advanced Arrow’s ideas. Buchanan’s dismissal of the reasonableness of the social welfare function concept altogether likely contributed to many libertarians accepting Arrow’s theorem in a knee-jerk fashion. Yet, the market process itself operates under the guidance of a particular social welfare function (as Arrow understood, despite Buchanan arguing the opposite). Thus, libertarians who accept Buchanan and Arrow’s ideas inadvertently reject the process underlying the market, which forms the foundation of modern civilization.
Buchanan’s Stance on Deficits and Debt: During Buchanan’s active years as a researcher, Keynesian economics dominated academic discourse. Keynesians at that time viewed government deficits as essentially costless during periods of resource idleness. Buchanan, by contrast, endeavored to resuscitate the common man’s belief that deficits burden future generations. While the Keynesians probably exaggerated their case, the reality is that current resources in the form of land, labor and capital must be marshalled to “finance” any increase in government expenditure. In that sense, larger deficits are “paid for” today and do not necessarily burden our children and grandchildren. The government issues bonds to pay for deficits, it is true, but when the payment comes due, some future taxpayer or bond buyer ultimately finances the payment. Moreover, the government can, in its unique position, perpetually roll over its obligations, thereby avoiding ever having to “pay back” some debts. (Granted, this is contingent on obligations not ballooning out of control.) The crux of how deficits impact the future lies not in the issuance of paper bonds, but in the nature of the spending, specifically the break down between consumption and investment, as well as the form investment takes. Moreover, just as with public spending, a substantial amount of private spending can be wasteful too. Buchanan’s influence has likely led libertarians to focus too much on deficits and debt, rather than on the character of spending—both public and private.
Undeniably, Buchanan has made positive contributions to economics, particularly in the field of public choice. However, it was probably inevitable that someone would eventually recognize the applicability of economic concepts to politics. Buchanan’s elite academic credentials and impressive publication record made him well-positioned to seize the opportunity, resulting in his Nobel recognition. Yet, if not Buchanan, would it not simply have been someone else?
Friedrich Hayek’s observations about the prize resonate here. The Nobel can unduly amplify the recipient’s influence, especially in areas where their wisdom might be less profound than in the domain that earned them their reputation. Buchanan cautioned us against taking an overly-optimistic view of politics. It’s time libertarians removed the rose-tinted glasses and saw Buchanan’s ideas in their true light.
James Broughel is a Senior Fellow at the Competitive Enterprise Institute with a focus on innovation and dynamism.
READER COMMENTS
Richard W Fulmer
Sep 20 2023 at 2:45pm
It seems to me that there can be subjective costs as well as objective costs. For example, building a road costs quantifiable amounts of cement, rebar, wire, water, energy, and labor. On the other hand, building the road also costs the opportunity to build an airstrip with those same resources. While one airstrip is quantifiable, what I really want from an airstrip are the benefits of its use, and those benefits are subjective. So, the opportunity cost of forgoing the airstrip are the subjective benefits lost.
David Henderson
Sep 20 2023 at 3:30pm
You write:
But isn’t that future taxpayer one of our children or grandchildren?
Thomas Hutcheson
Sep 21 2023 at 8:36am
The “burden,” if there is one, is if the NPV of the expenditure is less than the NPV of the expenditure the would have occurred were it not for the borrowing. Future income is lower. That is a “burden” on “future generations.” 🙂
Will Melick
Sep 20 2023 at 4:23pm
In Public Principles of Public Debt, Buchanan argues that burdens can only be borne by individuals, not by non-sentient entities such as “society” or the “government”. A government bond willingly purchased today by an individual does not create a burden as the exchange was made voluntarily and moves the bondholder to a preferred position. However, the taxes levied to service the debt are not a voluntary transaction undertaken by the taxpayer. The compulsory tax is a burden. A closer reading of Buchanan (particularly Chapter 4 of Public Principles of Public Debt) is in order.
Thomas Hutcheson
Sep 20 2023 at 6:14pm
Nice reflections which inspire some of my own.
“This can be attributed to the fact that public choice theory takes a more realistic view of government benevolence than does mainstream economics.”
Maybe the reason is that fee of PCT’s problems have surfaced because, unlike standard welfare economics, it has so seldom been employed to design policies. 🙂
“explain the lack of progress in Austrian economics in recent decades. ”
I’ve always struggled to understand what is different about “Austrian economics.” A quick reading of your link to Boettke’s post confirms my lack of understanding. His ten points are very general and nothing jumps out from them that’s seems inconsistent with welfare economics except perhaps the reluctance to attempt to measure marginal costs and benefits.
“In that sense, larger deficits are “paid for” today and do not necessarily burden our children and grandchildren.”
Your refutation is too strong. First, the effect of a “deficit” is only the combined effects of the taxing and spending decisions that go into it; every “deficit” is different.
Second, the idea of a deficit that burdens future generations can best be understood as a spending decision whose net present value is 0, then indeed future income is reduced which might be said to “burden” future generations. If, however, the NPV of the spending decision exceeds the NPV of the foregone activity, the “deficit” becomes not a burden but a boon to future generations.
“Keynesians at that time viewed government deficits as essentially costless during periods of resource idleness.”
Fair enough. A better view is that resource idleness means that the NPV of a potential spending decision when evaluated using marginal costs is greater than when evaluated at market prices. Thus, it more likely that a deficit will result in the transfer of resources from a higher NPV activity to a lower NPV activity. So the “deficit” while not costless is less costly.
Jon Murphy
Sep 21 2023 at 1:35pm
This seems to me to be a rather poor standard by which to judge a theory, at least if one treats science as, well, a science rather than simply a tool for planning. Any good theory should describe, to a reasonable degree, natural phenomenon and help offer predictions. That level of understanding can reasonably include knowing when planning is not possible.
Thomas Hutcheson
Sep 23 2023 at 11:05pm
So all the policies that have been designed without explicitly using Public Choice theory are examples of it being USED to exclude its use? 🙂
Jon Murphy
Sep 25 2023 at 5:55pm
Huh?
David Henderson
Sep 20 2023 at 7:25pm
You write:
I don’t see how. In a market, I trade with you. We both gain. So my welfare improves, as does yours. Is that what you mean by “a particular social welfare function” or do you have something else in mind?
Richard Fulmer
Sep 21 2023 at 1:17pm
The term “social welfare function” is vague enough that just about anything can be stuffed into it. Perhaps the establishment of the rule of law, recognition and protection of private property rights, and contract law administration could be considered a social welfare function.
Jon Murphy
Sep 21 2023 at 1:38pm
I’m not sure:
1) It’s fair to call Murray Rothbard a disciple of Buchanan given that Rothbardian economics at times explicitly (and often implicitly) rejects public choice analysis
2) It’s fair to blame Rothbardian misterpretation on Buchanan.
David Henderson
Sep 21 2023 at 2:30pm
I wondered why you were discussing Rothbard because I neglected to follow the link. Sure enough, it is a link to an article by Rothbard. The article doesn’t even mention Buchanan.
I knew Murray pretty well from about 1974 to the early 1980s and I don’t think he ever would have called himself a disciple of Buchanan. He was a discipline of nobody, with the possible exception of Mises.
Brandon
Sep 21 2023 at 3:40pm
[Rothbard] was a [disciple] of nobody, with the possible exception of Mises.
Is this a good thing or a bad thing?
David Henderson
Sep 21 2023 at 6:20pm
You write:
It’s a thing.
I’m challenging James’s claim. I’m not evaluating whether one should be a disciple.
nobody.really
Sep 23 2023 at 1:45am
True–but alas, he would not complete his training. I urged him not to give in to hate, for that way leads to the Dark Side, but he insisted on rescuing Hans and Leia. Greatly disappointed I was….
Sam Branthoover
Sep 29 2023 at 1:27am
Buchanan’s Cost and Choice draws a line between “choice-influencing costs” and “choice-influenced” cost. The former is is considered ex ante, and is what we’d call opportunity costs. The latter is perhaps what you’d call accounting costs; both are useful, Buchanan wouldn’t say otherwise.
In economics, cost is certainly not objective in any way.
Lyle Sande Zerkin
Oct 5 2023 at 11:32am
Why is a choice not taken considered a cost?
Are not costs made by actual decisions and not from the conjectures about the many possibilities of other choices?
Seems logical that a choice not taken cannot be assigned a tangible value because it was not deemed worthy of a subjective choice. We can conjecture logically and subjectively about alternative choices, but are those not taken actually ‘costs’ or just losers in the choice among alternatives?
Perhaps I’m missing something in the definition of cost as something actual, tangible, and real?
Comments are closed.