Like David Henderson, I was saddened to learn of the unfortunate death of Jeffrey Friedman. He was the founder of Critical Review, a journal I always find interesting, as well as the author of what I think is the most persuasive explanation of the 2008 financial crisis published so far. He was also a strong critic of both the economics profession and libertarianism, which makes him (to me) deeply interesting and engaging to read. I was very eager to read what turned out to be his final book, Power Without Knowledge: A Critique of Technocracy, as soon as it was released. I happened to have re-read it recently, and I will be putting together a series of posts reviewing the book.
First, a stylistic note is in order. While I find Friedman’s ideas engaging, his writing style flows like a river of bricks. Here’s a typical sentence:
The waters are only muddied if we conceptualize this inter-individual process of culture production as supra-individual, as when we pit intersubjectivity against subjectivity by omitting a factor that makes both ideational homogeneity and ideational heterogeneity possible: communication among individual human subjects.
You might want to skip this book if 350 pages of that kind of prose don’t appeal to you. That note having been made, let’s begin with an overview.
Friedman wishes to critically examine technocracy. Helpfully, he provides a clear definition of what he means by that term:
A polity that aims to solve, mitigate, or prevent social and economic problems among its people (henceforth, for convenience, their “social problems.”)
Now that he’s defined what a technocracy is, who are the technocrats? Friedman applies a broad brush here, classifying as technocrats not only putative experts, but also ordinary citizens who engage in political activity with the intent of achieving social goals. From here, he gives each group a distinctive classification:
In the meantime, let us define as “technocrats” all political actors who make knowledge claims (express or tacit) about the scope, causes of, and cures for social problems – whether these actors are trained, credentialed specialists or not. In turn, let us call “epistocrats” either trained, credentialed specialists (or any other political actors) who claim to have technocratic knowledge unavailable to ordinary citizens. Finally, let us call “citizen-technocrats” political actors who have non-esoteric opinions – explicit or tacit – about the scope, causes of, and cures for social problems.
By Friedman’s definitions, technocracy isn’t inherently an antidemocratic system where elites attempt to steer society. Instead:
What distinguishes this type of regime from others is not the number of its personnel in proportion to the population being governed – “the few” versus “the many” – but the nature of the regime’s mission: to solve, mitigate, and prevent social problems.
Friedman expects his inclusion of ordinary citizens as technocrats will be controversial:
Empirically oriented political scientists might scoff at the notion that ordinary citizens should be counted as technocrats…because they doubt that ordinary citizens are equipped to weigh policies’ costs against their benefits.
Against this concern, Friedman replies:
I am suggesting only that [citizens] political decisions are heavily influenced by perceptions of whether or not public policies can be expected to “work,” or are already “working”…Consider the well-established tendency of ordinary twentieth-century US citizens to vote retrospectively: that is, on the basis of whether the incumbent candidate or party has prevented or mitigated important social problems such as inflation, unemployment, or war. Retrospection of this sort is an all-things-considered form of cost-benefit analysis. Retrospective voters are tacitly claiming to know whether technocratic policies have produced good economic or foreign-policy consequences overall.
Having offered definitions of both technocracy and technocrats, Friedman sets out to examine the legitimacy of technocracy. His goal is not to raise an external critique of technocracy, as a libertarian might by arguing the project is illegitimate due to normative beliefs about the proper scope of government. Instead, he raises an internal critique – is technocracy workable according to its own purpose, as defined above? If a technocracy can’t reliably achieve the intended aims, or if those aims can be achieved by lower cost means, then technocracy would be internally illegitimate by its own standards.
Friedman identifies four different types of knowledge technocrats would need to achieve the goals of technocracy:
Type 1. Knowledge of which social problems are not only real but significant, in the sense that they affect large numbers of people – or small numbers intensely. (This amounts to the negative-utilitarian benefits to be achieved by solving, preventing, or mitigating problems.)
Type 2. Knowledge of what is causing the significant problems, and (preferably) knowledge of what might cause significant problems in the future.
Type 3. Knowledge of which technocratic actions can efficaciously solve, mitigate, or prevent the significant problems.
Type 4. Knowledge of the costs of efficacious solutions, including not only anticipated costs but those that are not intended, and thus not anticipated.
(As a side note, while I’ve argued it’s sensible to speak of costs that are unintended but still anticipated, by Friedman’s lights, all unintended costs are also unanticipated. Given that this is a review of his book, I’ll be using those terms according to his stipulated definitions.)
Without accurate type 1 knowledge, technocrats might expend considerable resources attempting to solve nonexistent or minor problems, preventing resources from being used to solve real or larger ones. Even with accurate type 1 knowledge, lacking type 2 knowledge will cause technocratic solutions to be useless or counterproductive. An example would be a doctor who knows the symptoms (accurate type 1 knowledge) but misdiagnoses the disease causing those symptoms (inaccurate type 2 knowledge). The treatments the doctor applies in this case will be wasted effort at best, and possibly harmful or fatal. Even with accurate type 1 and 2 knowledge, without accurate type 3 knowledge, technocratic policies will “devote scarce resources to inefficacious solutions, indirectly causing unintended problems by reducing our ability to implement efficacious solutions.” And finally, type 4 knowledge is needed to ensure that the cure isn’t worse than the disease.
However, Friedman doesn’t want to put forth an “unrealistically demanding” standard, and sets the bar at what seems like a reasonable level:
As a human enterprise, technocracy should not be held to standards of perfection…Thus, I suggest that as a working assumption, we deem a technocratic regime internally legitimate if it tends to do more good, overall, than the harm it creates in the form of costs, including unintended ones. According to this criterion, technocratic decision makers need to know, more often than not, how to establish the existence of social problems, how to roughly prioritize them according to their significance, how to discern their causes, and how to solve them well enough to do more good than the costs these solutions generate. This standard of adequacy cuts technocrats a great deal of slack without licensing too many policy backfires, invisible costs, and misguided missiles.
Thus, the stage is set for Friedman’s review of technocratic legitimacy. Over the next several posts, I’ll summarize the ideas Friedman uses to examine this question and the conclusions he reaches. I’ll wrap up by reviewing what I learned from this book, where he changed my mind, and where I find shortcomings in his argument.
Kevin Corcoran is a Marine Corps veteran and a consultant in healthcare economics and analytics and holds a Bachelor of Science in Economics from George Mason University.
READER COMMENTS
Kevin Corcoran
Jan 5 2023 at 2:05pm
A note for the curious!
While the posts in this series will be significantly longer than my usual blog post, inevitably a large portion of Friedman’s argument will be left on the proverbial cutting room floor. As questions arise, I’ll be checking back in and doing my best to answer them according to the argument the book presents, which may or may not overlap with my actual views in a given case.
Mactoul
Jan 5 2023 at 9:45pm
I wonder if any instance of a non-technocratic regime is provided.
Is it something like a closed society that is ruled by honor codes or religion?
Gene
Jan 6 2023 at 9:18am
Agreed. I’d like to know how he defines the alternatives to technocracy.
Kevin Corcoran
Jan 6 2023 at 11:36am
Hey Mactoul –
Good question. The first point of clarification I’d bring up is that it isn’t a binary choice, where societies are either technocratic or non-technocratic. It’s more of a sliding scale, where societies can be relatively more or relatively less technocratic. Additionally, Friedman largely limits his analysis to the United States, given that it’s the society he knows best.
Stepping back, there’s a more abstract point that’s definitely worth clearing up early on. You ask if a non-technocratic society would be something like “a closed society that is ruled by honor codes or religion”, which (and correct me if I’m misunderstanding you!) makes me think you’re envisioning technocracy as laws or legislation in some general sense, so for a society to be non-technocratic would entail it being some kind of stateless society. But there is a fundamental difference between laws or legislation in some general sense, and technocratic policy initiatives specifically.
Consider two societies, Society A and Society B, each of which has one social problem, let’s say “poverty.” Society A doesn’t establish specific, targeted program to alleviate poverty – it just establishes general rules of conduct, and allows solutions to poverty to emerge, perhaps from economic growth, perhaps from mutual aid societies, or other emergent means. Society B, by contrast, implements a policy which identifies the “root cause” of poverty as being [insert cause here, maybe poor education, discrimination, social dysfunction, etc], and proposes this “root cause” be dealt with by means of [insert targeted intervention here, better schools, social education programs, welfare, etc], and as a result of this intervention, [insert root cause here] will be ameliorated, leading to [predicted outcome here]. Society A would be very much in the non-technocratic camp, while Society B would be very much in the technocratic camp.
One way to see how this works according to Friedman’s system is that the policies of Society B, unlike Society A, are specifically motivated by claims of technocratic knowledge. The technocrats of Society B are claiming to have identified a real and significant social problem (poverty), identified the underlying cause of this problem (lack of education or whatever), claimed their specific, targeted intervention will effectively offset this underlying cause in a predictable way that is knowable in advance, and that the anticipated results will both be effectively achieved and not be outweighed by both the known and unknown costs of the program.
So technocratic policy initiatives are different from the general rules of society. As Friedman writes, “the aim of technocracy is to advance social and economic welfare by addressing such problems as unemployment, inflation, failing schools, a dysfunctional health care system, drug addiction”, etc. Among the “wide array of ills,” technocracy will offer “at least one programmatic solution. These programs are paradigmatically technocratic because they are designed to solve, mitigate, or prevent discrete social problems.” For example, in “United States, there were 92 federal poverty-related programs as of 2014, in addition to many more state and local programs”, and these “technocratic poverty-related programs take aim at specific difficulties experienced by the poor, such as the unavailability of affordable housing.” Part of what makes these programs technocratic is that they “prescribe the needs to be addressed” as well as “the means by which they are addressed.” Thus, the approach to poverty in the United States has shifted from being less technocratic towards more technocratic, as things have shifted away from mutual aid and towards the welfare state.
[One of these days, I’ll learn to write shorter comments, I swear!]
Mactoul
Jan 6 2023 at 8:35pm
Kevin,
That was most clarifying. I was going on an off-tangent and was wondering about pre-modern societies for which technical and social progress was not a major point. I suppose they would qualify as non-technocratic but the case of modern non-technocratic societies is much more interesting.
Dylan
Jan 6 2023 at 6:23pm
Thanks Kevin for this interesting introduction to a new topic for me.
I tend to lean technocratic, and by this definition it seems almost inconceivable to not be technocratic, as what is a polity for, if not to solve or at least mitigate social and economic problems?
This example confuses me a little though. What if you are looking to mitigate poverty, and you determine that the cause (or at least the cause the government is best able to address) is over regulation? Occupational licensing is preventing poor people from getting jobs, zoning laws make housing unaffordable, drug laws disproportionately punish the poor, and on and on. So the technocrats look to reduce regulation with the goal of alleviating poverty. It seems by Friedman’s definition this would be a technocratic approach to policy, no?
Kevin Corcoran
Jan 6 2023 at 10:31pm
I think a key feature that distinguishes a technocratic polity from a non-technocratic one would be how the policies of that polity interact with the members of that society. Like I described above, a non-technocratic society can still have laws and legislation, but those laws are, in general, reactive to the citizens – they don’t affect a citizen until a citizen crosses that line. The rules set boundaries within which citizens are able to act, thus setting the stage, but the rules are not used to steer behavior on that stage in order to reach specific outcomes that have been designated in advance. In a technocratic society, policies are proactive towards the citizens, not only keeping them within the bounds of the game but proactively seeking to alter how they play, in order to steer people’s behavior in a way that will achieve specific outcomes that have been designated in advance.
Yes, that is correct. About midway through the book, Friedman spends some time examining the debate among economists about the effect and desirability of minimum wage policy. By Friedman’s lights, this is a technocratic policy debate, and economists on both sides of that debate are acting as technocrats.
Kevin Corcoran
Jan 8 2023 at 8:36am
Hello again, Dylan!
On reflection, I realized my answer to your first question was off – or, more accurately, I answered a slightly different question. I think the answer I gave was more suited towards clarifying what distinguishes a technocratic society from a non-technocratic one, but that’s not useful to answer your first question. You specifically asked “what is a polity for, if not to solve or at least mitigate social and economic problems,” which isn’t really answered by what I said the first time around. I’m going to blame lack of coffee, because that allows me to rationalize drinking more coffee.
In any case, it’s true that most of us would agree a polity (or civil society, or social organizations, or whatever) are desired at least in part because they can help us mitigate social problems. However, the distinct feature a technocratic polity is found in one key word in Friedman’s definition: “polity that aims to solve, mitigate, or prevent social and economic problems among its people”. Just because a society is non-technocratic doesn’t mean social organization doesn’t serve the function of mitigating social problems – it means that social organization isn’t deliberately aimed in targeted ways, at the level of the polity, to achieve that function, according to technocratic design. To tie it back to the book I referenced in my reply to Mactoul, one might say that a polity that lays out general rules of conduct, but does not attempt to determine specific outcomes, helps solve the social problem of poverty by setting a stage that allows the emergence of a variety of solutions to that problem, such as the mutual aid societies and fraternal organizations described in the book From Mutual Aid to the Welfare State.
In that way, one can say this polity is non-technocratic, in there is not a specific, targeted aim at the level of the polity to solve the social problem of poverty comparable to the many federal and state level poverty relief programs Friedman cites, and similarly, there aren’t any programs at the level of the polity that specifically “prescribe the needs to be addressed” or determine “the means by which they are addressed.” This doesn’t mean the polity doesn’t serve the purpose of solving or mitigating social problems – it just means social problems are alleviated in a non-technocratic way.
So asking what a polity is for, if not to solve or mitigate social problems, doesn’t by itself speak in favor technocratic society vs a non-technocratic one. Rather, the key question is the means by which social problems are addressed. To the extent that one advocates a polity actively aiming at solving specific, identified social problems through programs prescribing the means by which they are to be addressed, one is technocratic. But simply believing a polity is for solving or mitigating social problems doesn’t in and of itself commit one to technocracy as the means to handle those problems.
So one can agree with you that a polity is for mitigating social problems, without necessarily advocating technocracy as the means to achieve this. The question of what a polity is for is a question about ends, but technocracy is an argument about means to achieve those ends.
Dylan
Jan 8 2023 at 7:23pm
Thanks Kevin. Really appreciate you taking the time to write such a well thought out response (2 of them even!).
I’m still left with the sense that this definition of technocratic is so broad that it loses meaning in the present world we live in. Would there be an example of a modern nation state that is not technocratic? Or is it all a matter of degree, where all states are technocracies at some level, but some are more so than others?
Kevin Corcoran
Jan 9 2023 at 11:34am
This is correct. It would be useful to think of “technocracy” in the same way we might talk about the term “free market.” There aren’t (to my knowledge!) any societies right now that are purely non-technocratic, just like there aren’t any that are pure free markets. Still, it makes sense to talk about societies that are relatively more or less technocratic, just as it makes sense to talk about and compare societies with relatively more free markets or less free markets.
Additionally, even though all societies use technocratic means to some degree for at least some social problems, not every social problem is handled technocratically in every society. So we can say “While neither Society A nor Society B are purely nontechnocratic, specific social problem X is handled technocratically in A and non-technocratically in B.” For example, one useful social mechanism is reputation. In the United States, a company’s reputation is subject to word of mouth, or aggregated in customer reviews on services like Yelp, or graded by private organizations like the Better Business Bureau or Consumer Reports. These are decentralized, nontechnocratic means for regulating business reputation. By contrast, in China, there is an elaborate Social Credit System that centrally tracks and assigns a Social Credit Score ranking institutions, individuals, and businesses for trustworthiness. So we can say in China, the issue of trustworthiness and reputation is handled technocratically, while in the United States, the issue is handled non-technocratically.
Dylan
Jan 9 2023 at 2:13pm
Thanks Kevin, very helpful. Looking forward to reading part 2.
Comments are closed.