On Tuesday, in a previous post titled “Presuppositions,” I shared this picture:
and wrote:
Four cards are shown, each card showing a character on the side shown, namely A, B, 2, and 3, respectively.
Consider the following proposition:
Proposition P: If one side of a card has a vowel, then on the other it has an even number.
To establish that none of these four cards falsifies Proposition P, which cards must one turn over?
At the original post, several people graciously shared their thoughts in the comment field. Thanks to you all for your valuable contributions!
I encountered the picture at the home of Per Skedinger, who presented us with the puzzle. Different answers were suggested by members of our dinner group.
Proposition P would be falsified by a card that on one side had a vowel and on the other side did not have an even number. The question is, which of the four cards may falsify Proposition P?
At the dinner, one member of our group included the “2” card in his answer, I think because he took “If one side of a card has a vowel” to mean “If and only if one side of a card has a vowel.” But Proposition P does not say if and only if. So that reason for including the “2” card is faulty.
At the dinner, I—like some of the commenters at the first post—suggested, the “A” card and the “3” card. But discussion made me realize that I was presupposing a condition that I didn’t have great grounds for, namely, that all cards have a letter on one side and a number on the other. Once we drop that condition, we see that we need to turn over the “B” card, for it may have a vowel on the other side. (Kudos to commenters Joel, Capt. J, robc, and Francisco.)
Our formulations always involve inarticulate assumptions or presuppositions.
Among the commenters at the first post, almost all operate on the assumption that we might read the card-side “data” as showing that one card has only an A on it, one only a B, one only a 2, and one only a 3.
But are we certain that the “2” card-side has only a 2 on it? We do not see the entire side. Maybe there is a vowel or an odd number in the unshown portion of the “2” card-side.
And you could go further, and wonder about teeny-weeny characters (“the fine print”). And Capt. J came up with some other creative responses to the problem.
If you keep digging you can always argue that “the facts” are theory-laden.
Suppose we turn over all four cards and find that none falsifies Proposition P. Does that mean that Proposition P has been verified?
If Proposition P refers, not just to the four cards, but to some larger set of cards of which the four are but elements, then Proposition P has been confirmed for those four cards but has not been fully verified.
I take this opportunity to excurse a bit.
My thinking in philosophy of science tends toward Thomas Kuhn, Michael Polanyi, and Deirdre McCloskey, and I read David Hume along such lines. The tendency is skeptical about claims of a strict logic of science, a principle for demarcating between science and non-science, or a definite scientific method. (If I am not mistaken, the Kuhn work most relevant to these matters is his 1970 piece quoted here.)
Elsewhere, I have written:
A sect might tailor its language so as to ensure the analyticity of the any of the following sentences: “The triangle has three sides.” “The child was born of a mother.” “The sum of the assets equals liabilities plus equity.” “Y = C + I + G + NX.” “The person maximized his utility.” “If transaction costs were negligible and parties were aware of the relevant opportunities, those parties achieved an efficient outcome.” “The moral sentiment relates to a sympathy.”
For such a language community, the analytic statement in question would be non-falsifiable. Does that mean it’s not scientific? Here I think of something Thomas Schelling wrote: “It is sometimes said, in textbooks and in learned volumes, that these accounting statements, being unfalsifiable, do not count as science. I don’t care.”
Here, someone might respond: Well, the falsifiability criterion is about demarcating between science and non-science for empirical statements, and those analytic statements are not empirical. So, by themselves, they don’t speak to the merit of the falsifiability criterion.
I then say: A language community maintaining one of those analytic sentences may be taken to be saying, tacitly: Maintaining the analytic sentence is good. (Didn’t Gary Becker say that about one of them? Didn’t Adam Smith say it about another?) That statement, though vague, would seem to be empirical, and falsifiable, in principle. The big challenge then is in providing falsifying evidence. The challenging researcher must show that maintaining the analytic sentence is not good. Here we see why the philosophy of science merges with the history and sociology of science: Did the way in which the sociology of judgment actually unfolded conduce to the good? Was it perverted by certain forces, as in Soviet science or the governmentalization of science generally? Michael Polanyi wrote about the conditions under which the sociology of judgment conduced to the good.
Like grammar, strict logic and the hunt for falsifying evidence have their place, but they leave important things underdetermined. It’s fine to call foul on errors in strict logic, and it’s fine to present purportedly falsifying evidence, but it’s misguided to think that strict logic and the hunt for falsifying evidence alone can establish important claims. Science is a moral activity. It is purposeful, interpretive, even aesthetic, and the rules of aesthetics are rather different from the rules of grammar (the differentness is presented in Figure 6.3 here). A blank page contains neither violations of grammar nor errors in logic, but it does not satisfy the standards of good science.
Saying that science is interpretive is not saying that science is arbitrary. It is not saying that no interpretation is better than another.
I have often wondered about the following proposition:
Proposition R: No half-way serious, reputable thinker has ever said that no interpretation is better than another.
I don’t know whether Proposition R is true. (Of course, “half-way serious, reputable thinker” is vague, but we have to draw a line somewhere.)
Comments are open. In particular, if you can falsify Proposition R, please provide the falsifying evidence in the comment section.
READER COMMENTS
Stéphane Couvreur
Aug 7 2021 at 12:28pm
I like the idea of tiny characters hidden in the corners 😉
That’s thinking outside the box. Didn’t see that one coming!
Jerry Brown
Aug 7 2021 at 3:09pm
I don’t know exactly what ‘Proposition R’ is trying to propose because the language is a little ambiguous. But I think John Maynard Keynes took himself at least halfway seriously and was a ‘reputable thinker’ in his time. And some people have interpreted some of his work as saying that where there is a lot of uncertainty it actually is better to just say you don’t or can’t know, rather than come up with an explanation that is likely to be wrong.
But not being a reputable thinker myself, I have no idea whether this counts as falsification. And sadly, I’m not even sure about what you are asking.
Michael Rulle
Aug 8 2021 at 11:32am
What is the answer? 🙂 I am ignoring the trick stuff—-assuming what you see is what you have.
I am not even sure of the question.
It seems like the proposition is a “vowel is always matched with even numbers”. It says nothing about any other combination. Therefore, if one finds a card where a vowel is not matched with with an even number, the proposition is falsified. So all cards need to be turned over. A may have an odd number. B may have an even number. 2 may have a consonant. E may have a vowel. Therefore, we cannot know if this is falsifiable. It might be—-but we cannot know a priori if it is falsifiable.
But I am guessing I am wrong——only because it seems to much like the Monte Hall problem. In other words it seems “obvious”—-which is a great clue that is is not!
Michael Rulle
Aug 8 2021 at 11:46am
What is the answer? 🙂 I am ignoring the trick stuff—-assuming what you see is what you have. Also assuming a letter has a number and vice versa on the other side. This makes it “harder”.
I am not even sure of the question.
It seems like the proposition is a “vowel is always matched with even numbers”.
It says nothing about any other combination.
Therefore, if one finds a card where a vowel is not matched with with an even number, the proposition is falsified.
So all cards need to be turned over. A may have an even number. B may have an odd number. 2 may have a vowel. 3 may have a consonent . Therefore, we cannot know if this is falsifiable. It might be—-but we cannot know a priori if it is falsifiable.
But I am guessing I am wrong——only because it seems to much like the Monte Hall problem. In other words it seems “obvious”—-which is a great clue that is is not!
Michael Rulle
Aug 8 2021 at 12:14pm
My first answer was supposed to be erased. Sorry! It is my second answer that I propose.
Michael Rulle
Aug 8 2021 at 12:01pm
PS
I assume that a “vowel is always matched with even numbers” is equivalent to “even numbers are always matched with vowels”. The reason is there is no statement with regard to the order in which one sees the two sides. Just because it shows one side, it does not mean the order in which it is seen is determinative of anything. Unless specifically said.
My first answer had a typo—-E should have been 3
Michael Rulle
Aug 8 2021 at 12:32pm
Re: proposition R
Cannot falsify it—-but I am positive I could. Need more data than I have time for. It is literally impossible for a halfway good thinker to not make a mistake. That alone falsifies it. So I am sure there have been some problems where someone has said for a particular problem one answer is as good as another —-even if not true——but it was complex enough —-or he was momentarily careless enough —-that it was said.
Or——-Einstein said that for certain problems Newton was as accurate as Relativity and I am sure he said for those problems one interpretation was as good as another.
Monte
Aug 9 2021 at 12:03pm
It has been argued that there is no logical explanation for evil. Might the concept of evil falsify Proposition R, in that no interpretation is better than another?
Ross
Aug 11 2021 at 2:43pm
Dan, I think you’re wrong. You DO have to turn over both the A card and the 2 card. It has nothing to do with iff vs if.
Here’s an easy way to see it. Assume on the opposite side of the 2 card is an “I”. And turn it over before beginning. Now, the same cards differently arranged show “A”, “B”, “I”, “3” at the beginning. IF cards with vowels must have an EVEN number on the opposite side, you have to turn over the first and third card, just as some told you initially. They are right.
Were the problem instead IFF, THEN you’d have to turn over EVERY card. You’d have to turn over vowel cards to make sure they had an even number on the other side. You’d have to turn over consonant cards to make sure they did NOT have an even number on the other side. You’d have to turn over all even cards to make sure they had vowels on the other side and all odd cards to make sure they didn’t.
Daniel Klein
Aug 11 2021 at 5:31pm
Hi Ross. The point of your third paragraph is well taken. If someone misunderstood “if” as “iff,” and then followed through on the basis of iff, then such person would say that we need to turn over, not only the “A,” “2,” and “3” cards, but also the “B” card, a point that I do not include. Maybe you’re right that the “2” suggestion did not spring from misunderstand “if” as “iff.” When people include the “2” card maybe sometimes that is because they misunderstand the nature of the question and instead think that finding confirmations or instantiations of Proposition P is called for.
As for your second paragraph, I’m afraid I don’t follow you there.
Comments are closed.