In the analysis of market processes, the concept of externalities has long invoked strong public policy implications among economists regarding the role of government in addressing their alleged presence, or lack thereof.
It is for this reason that analyses of externalities have preoccupied economists, at least since A.C. Pigou. The more important question, however, is how do they matter for economics?
In an excellent and thought-provoking article recently written by Don Boudreaux and Roger Meiners (2019), they provide a comprehensive overview of the origins of the concept of externality, its evolution, and its classifications. Boudreaux and Meiners put forth a subtle though sophisticated argument that transcends how economists generally arrive at particular public policy implications regarding externalities. My goal here is not simply to summarize their point, but also to provide my own interpretation of their argument.
To summarize the concept briefly, an externality refers to a spillover cost borne by third parties to an exchange. Externalities arise when the market price at which a good is exchanged fails to account for the full cost (in the case of a negative externality) or benefits (in the case of a positive externality) of producing a good. Such costs or benefits are, therefore, not only involuntary, but more importantly, unexpected by third parties to the exchange. Externalities are indicative of a deviation from the ideal of perfectly competitive equilibrium, in which all potential gains from trade have been exhausted. Thus, the resulting “market failure” associated with externalities arises from the fact that “there exists a reallocation of resources, such as a change in the structure of market activities that will enrich society” (Boudreaux and Meiners, 2019, p. 21). This restructuring not only includes an adjustment in market prices to more fully concentrate the costs and benefits of exchange upon the relevant trading partners, but also, more importantly, an adjustment in the assignment of property rights, the exchange of which gives rise to exchange ratios, or market prices, in the first place. I will return to this last point later.
The fundamental aspect on which Boudreaux and Meiners focus is not the involuntary nature of externalities, but the degree to which they are expected or not. As they put it, “Externalities exist only when another party’s actions create unexpected spillover effects” (emphasis in original, 2019, p. 29).
Building on Alchian (1965) and Demsetz (1967), Boudreaux and Meiners make clear that property rights “are a bundle of expectations” (emphasis in original, Boudreaux and Meiners 2019, p. 31) about how individuals can choose to use, exclude, and exchange resources. The expectation in a market economy is that property rights allow “harm” to the exchange value of a good or service, but not to its physical characteristics.
Consider a barber who sets up shop in midtown Manhattan, assuming well-defined and enforced property rights, physical impediments to his expected ability to utilize his physical and human capital for providing haircuts constitutes an externality. For example, theft or other physical damage to the barber’s property rights are assumed to be prohibited. But, under these assumptions, he also has – or, as a reasonable person, should have – the expectation that a competing barber may “steal” away his clientele by providing a better haircut, thus reducing his income and the resale value of the capital he employs.
Here is where the concept of externality gets a bit tricky, and why “the term has become nearly meaningless due to its ubiquity,” according to Boudreaux and Meiners (2019, p. 3). Returning to the previous example, suppose that building construction is taking place on 5th Avenue, requiring the use of jackhammers. These jackhammers, no doubt, are a nuisance to the barber, and therefore might impede his ability to provide haircuts in a safe and productive manner. A bad haircut or the slip of a razor blade while shaving a client will result in a misallocation of resources in terms of “too much” building construction and “too few” haircuts and shaves than would otherwise be optimal. Is this indicative of a negative externality? Does this example prove that building construction should be taxed in order for contractors to take into account the noise pollution resulting from construction?
Not necessarily.
The key here is the role of expectations. No doubt, incurring the noise pollution from jackhammering was involuntary if the building contractors did not get the barber’s consent beforehand. However, we can reasonably conclude that when the barber chose to locate his shop in midtown Manhattan, one of the most densely populated islands on earth, he would have expected and anticipated such occurrences. The fact that he nevertheless located there implies that he expects the cost to him of this particular “externality” to be sufficiently low as to not overwhelm the prospect of greater expected monetary income derived from serving a larger and wealthier clientele than if he located in a less populated area outside the city.
What does this way of looking at externalities reveal about the welfare implications of the market process?
The fundamental point that Boudreaux and Meiners raise, as I understand it, is twofold. First, market processes are imperfect, meaning always in disequilibrium, and therefore imply that the expectations of individuals will never fully mutually coincide. If economists start in a world of disequilibrium as their analytic point of departure, then expectations about the costs and benefits of individual decision-making are never perfect (see Hayek 1937), in which case the concept of externalities, in an abstract sense, means everything and nothing. This implies, I would argue, that if the concept of externalities is to have any meaning and tractability, it must be grounded in an analysis of the particular expectations that individuals have in time and place. In doing so, it will provide the economist with a richer understanding of the public policy implications that follow from his or her analysis.
Secondly, to admit or to deny the presence of externalities is not analogous to admitting or denying the presence of market imperfection. Admitting the presence of externalities does not necessarily imply the necessity of government intervention. But, the absence of externalities does not necessarily imply Pareto efficiency in the allocation of resources either. It therefore does not follow that embracing one analytical point of departure or the other implies the dismissal of or appeal to government intervention as a corrective.
As I’ve written elsewhere, imperfect markets do not imply suboptimality or an inherent flaw as compared to the ideal of equilibrium. Rather, imperfection implies “incompleteness” and therefore that markets are processes incessantly moving towards completion. That completion process is facilitated by greater mutual coordination of expectations, requiring corrections in expectations, which makes market processes necessary to addresses misallocations of resources in the first place! As Boudreaux and Meiners make clear, “nothing said here suggests that the absence of spillovers implies a Pareto-optimal allocation of resources” (2019, p. 30). It simply implies the failure of the conditions of the market process to exist, not the existence of market failure (see Candela and Geloso 2020). “The problem, if one asserts there is a problem, is the structure of property rights” (Boudreaux and Meiners 2019, p. 30).
If I have correctly interpreted Boudreaux and Meiners, the question is not whether or not externalities matter for economists, but when they matter for economics, and how they matter for our analysis.
As an example to illustrate and conclude this point, let’s take the example of the solution devised by Julian Simon to the problem of airline overbooking (see Simon 1968). Generally speaking, airlines tend to overbook flights on the expectation that there will be a certain number of cancellations. Airline overbooking can then be reframed as problem of assigning property rights, since it creates a situation in which more than one individual has a claim on an assigned seat. When an airline involuntarily “bumps” an individual to another flight, can we conclude that represents an externality? Again, we must take into the context of time and place.
Indeed, the airline has generated a misallocation of resources through its decision-making. It exchanges a claim to a seat for money with a customer, but by assigning more than one customer to the same seat, there is a potential spillover cost on an individual bumped to a future flight, the full cost of which is not borne by the airline. However, we must conclude in this case that though bumping individuals to a future flight may be involuntary, it is not completely unexpected. Prior to the introduction of Simon’s auction proposal, an individual booking a flight could not rule out the possibility that a flight is overbooked. The anticipation of this possibility by individuals implies that this is not an example of an externality. However, to conclude this is not an externality does not imply this is a Pareto-optimal situation. There is indeed a misallocation of resources, since there are too many claimants to the available seats on a flight. Therefore, there is a profit opportunity to devise an institutional innovation to realize such potential Pareto improvements.
The introduction of the auction solution to the problem of airline overbooking can be understood as private property right solution, and therefore introduces new expectations between the airline and its customers about allocation of property rights. Given the transaction costs associated with correctly estimating the number of cancellations by customers, the introduction of the auction system (whether through a voucher or cash payment) grants all existing claimants to airline seats the ability to exchange, in effect creating private property rights in seats (Alchian 1965). Customers, in effect, not only become buyers of seats, but the auction system allows them to become potential sellers back to the airline in the case of overbooking. This exemplifies the point made by Phillip Wicksteed, namely that the supply curve for a good or service (in this airline seats) is part of the total demand curve for a good or service (see Wicksteed 1914, p. 13). More importantly, the exchange process generated through the auction system not only reduces the transaction costs associated with discovering the individuals with the lowest opportunity cost of moving to another flight (at a particular price that reflects such opportunity cost), it also reduces the transaction cost of economically calculating the minimum price necessary to pay an individual to be moved to a future flight. Such knowledge only arises in the context of the exchange of property rights (see Mises 1920 [1975]), which creates more consistent dovetailing of expectations between individuals.
Thus, the ability to assign private property rights in seats with the introduction of the auction system thereafter creates an expectation that individuals will be compensated if an airline mistakenly overbooks a flight. This brings me to the case of the United Airlines 3411 incident that took place on April 9, 2017, in which a passenger, Dr. Dao Duy Anh, was involuntarily dragged off the flight for refusal to give up his seat. This would seem to be a case of an externality, since the situation represents not only an involuntary cost borne unfortunately by the individual, but also because it was unexpected. Given the expectation that, through the auction system, an individual more willing to give up his or seat could likely have been discovered and paid a lower price than what Dr. Anh would have probably demanded as compensation for the airline’s error in overbooking.
Connecting this example back to Boudreaux and Meiners, the point here is that however one approaches this analysis, the existence or non-existence of externalities does not eliminate the fact that airline overbooking was representative of a misallocation of resources. And, the fact that this imperfection in the market process facilitated an institutional innovation to erode an existing inefficiency in the allocation of airline seats did not depend upon whether or not there existed an externality. And yet, the presence of an externality does not automatically presume a market failure, requiring government intervention, but a failure to secure the conditions of the market process, namely the voluntary exchange of property rights, due to government intervention. We can therefore conclude that the unfortunate circumstances that transpired during the United Airlines 3411 incident indicated the presence of a negative externality, but that this was a result of government failing to provide clear expectations about the security and enforcement property rights in airline seats, not a market failure.
The focus of analyses for economists, therefore, should not be to look backward at a presumed consistency or inconsistency in expectations between individuals, and then to pass normative judgment on it in terms of its conformity with Pareto-optimality or an efficient allocation of resources. Rather, the economist must always approach each analysis of any state of affairs as “nothing but a seething mass of unexploited maladjustments waiting to be corrected” (Kirzner 1979, p. 119), and focus on the constant adjustments that market processes facilitate in an open-ended world of uncertainty.
Rosolino Candela is a Senior Fellow in the F.A. Hayek Program for Advanced Study in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, and Associate Director of Academic and Student Programs at the Mercatus Center at George Mason University
Further References
Candela, Rosolino A., and Vincent J. Geloso. 2020. “The Lighthouse Debate and the Dynamics of Interventionism.” The Review of Austrian Economics 33(3): 289–314.
Hayek, F.A. 1937. “Economics and Knowledge.” Economica 4(13): 33–54.
Kirzner, Israel M. 1979. Perception, Opportunity, and Profit. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Mises, Ludwig von. 1920 [1975]. “Economic Calculation in the Socialist Commonwealth.” In F.A. Hayek, ed. Collectivist Economic Planning (pp. 87–130). Clifton, NJ: August M. Kelley.
READER COMMENTS
AMT
Sep 21 2020 at 3:51pm
So because it is expected that others will emit greenhouse gases, they are not an externality. GENIUS.
Jon Murphy
Sep 21 2020 at 4:36pm
Right. If it is expected, then you’ve either taken steps to mitigate the outside cost or decided that the benefits were not worth the costs of transacting. Either way, the externality is solved in the economic sense.
AMT
Sep 21 2020 at 5:58pm
There is a gigantic difference between saying there IS NOT an externality, and there is no optimal economic policy solution which alleviates the externality, due to transaction costs. That’s literally changing the definition of externality. This quote is clearly wrong.
The problem is clearly whether there is a solution for an individual to undertake, or if there is a solution for society to take, such as Pigouvian taxes, or subsidies for positive externalities. According to these “economists” the literal TEXTBOOK example of pollution is not an externality, simply because it is expected. That is just plain stupid. Of course externalities matter for economic analysis. You need to analyze whether the transaction costs make interventions to correct externalities worthwhile! This is the ultimate facepalm.
Jon Murphy
Sep 21 2020 at 8:20pm
Calm down. There’s no reason for name calling.
The textbook example is a pedagogical tool, but it is incomplete. Once we start dealing with the real world, with transaction costs and uncertainty, the textbook example gets more complicated. Ronald Coase won a Nobel Prize about this. And there’s also been a lot of work by other great economists like Demsetz, Dahlman, Alchian, etc.
One of the things Coase shows in his famous 1960 paper “The Problem of Social Cost” is that once transaction costs are taken into account, it’s not necessarily the case that externalities exist. What Dahlman shows in his 1979 paper “The Problem of Externality” is that once uncertainty is taken into account, we cannot easily claim the Externality wasn’t internalized.
Remember the textbook example: the optimal level of pollution is not zero.
Now, Don’s paper linked above does a deep dive of the literature. I suggest you read it.
AMT
Sep 22 2020 at 12:44pm
Nothing you say actually responds to my critique.
I never said that it doesn’t get more complicated than the textbook example, nevertheless, complicating the economic analysis doesn’t MAKE THE EXTERNALITY CEASE TO EXIST.
Coase does not say “once transaction costs are taken into account, it’s not necessarily the case that externalities EXIST.” (emphasis added)
I never said that the optimal level of pollution is zero.
“An externality is defined as a market failure. If there is not one, there is not the other.”
No. Quite obviously if transaction costs are high we may choose to do nothing about an externality. Again, and for the final time, that doesn’t mean there is NO externality. The definition of an externality is that there is a third party impacted, EXTERNAL to the transaction or activity.
If I see a dirty penny on the ground, and I decide it is not worthwhile to pick it up, that does not mean there is not a penny on the ground. This is not very complicated logic.
Jon Murphy
Sep 22 2020 at 2:35pm
The logic isn’t the problem here. It’s your understanding of what externalitites are. The penny on the ground is not a relevant comparison.
An externality is an unaccounted-for cost foisted upon a third party. If that cost is expected by the third party, then it is accounted for. It’s not an externality (indeed, it might not even be a cost). Coase takes Pigou to task over this point showing that much of what Pigou considers externality are not due to liability rules.
Jon Murphy
Sep 22 2020 at 4:43pm
There’s a trap here, AMT, that is very easy to fall into. And I think you’ve fallen into it. You’re confusing cost with consequence.
Colloquially, the word “cost” means anything bad/undesirable that happens. Economically, however, “cost” means foregone opportunities. “Consequence” refers more to bad/undesirable outcomes.
For example, economically speaking, having to deal with bad weather in an area is not a cost of living there. Living in New Hampshire does not have the cost blizzards. It’s the consequence. Tennis elbow is not a cost of playing tennis. It is a consequence.
“Cost” requires a choice to be made. “Consequences” are just part of life. We may not like them any more than the cost, but they are what they are.
Chapter 3 of Universal Economics goes into good detail here.
AMT
Sep 22 2020 at 5:30pm
Quote for me where Coase says this.
Quote for me any respected economics textbook that defines externalities using your definition. It never appeared in any of mine.
First, I never said anything about costs. I said externalities IMPACT third parties. Which, by the way, is exactly how even the source you just cited defines externalities.
Expectations don’t erase externalities.
But anyway, yeah, just redefine the words. “Opportunity cost” and “cost” are actually different terms with different meanings. Try inputting this person’s definition into “cost-benefit analysis” and see how that works.
AMT
Sep 23 2020 at 6:32pm
I’ll keep waiting.
I presume you no longer stand by your previous articles, since you have amended your definition of externality within the last year?
https://www.libertarianism.org/columns/tale-two-externalities-technical-pecuniary
Jon Murphy
Sep 23 2020 at 10:28pm
AMT:
In no particular order:
-No, my article at libertarianism.org does not contradict my point here. It is the same point.
Problem of Social Cost, 1960 Journal of Law and Economics. See also The Firm, The Market, and The Law, specifically Chapters 1 and 6.
Oh Geez. Mankiw. Cowen and Tabarrok. Pigou. Marshall. Stiglitz. Alchian and Allen. Any and all textbooks. That is the definition of an externality.
Externalities are, by definition, costs.
No. Alchian and Allen, Chapter 3. Or any textbook, really.
Yeah, see this is where your confusion lies. You do not understand the definition of externality. As Rosolino explains, it’s very subtle. You’re falling exactly into the trap I said you were.
AMT
Sep 23 2020 at 11:05pm
I have read Coase and you are clearly misinterpreting him because he doesn’t say this. Trying to hide by eschewing an actual quote won’t save you here.
So I guess positive externalities are negative costs? When you are willing to state such nonsensical contradictions, and flagrantly misstate what both I wrote and what others have written, I know it is a waste of time taking anything you say seriously.
Jon Murphy
Sep 23 2020 at 11:58pm
No, I don’t think you have. Or rather, if you have, you probably misunderstood him. His entire point of the famous 1960 paper is that externalities can be internalized once transaction costs are taken into account. Buchanan & Stubblebine and Dahlman later emphasize this point, as does Demsetz.
We’re talking negative externalities. Please stay on topic.
Look, I’ve said all I can say on the matter. Your attitude tells me you do not have a desire to be serious to recognize your mistakes here. I’ll shall waste no more time on this suffice to say this:
It is possible that I and everyone else who study externalities in depth are wrong on this matter and you are the only one to realize it. But is very unlikely, especially given your misunderstanding of cost.
AMT
Sep 24 2020 at 12:38am
I said:
The author of this blog post said:
More evidence of your reading comprehension! No wonder you didn’t understand Coase.
Mark Z
Sep 22 2020 at 12:46am
I think it’s actually the opposite: absent transaction costs, the market will spontaneously reach the optimum without public policy intervention. The case for intervention hinges on transaction costs.
I agree that they are redefining the term ‘externality.’ It would be more accurate if they had instead said that, inasmuch as an externality is expected, there is no market failure, not that there is no externality. The reasoning being that if everyone know Acme Co. is polluting the river, and expect it to continue to do so indefinitely, and this harms a downstream village, then if it is worth it for the village to pay them to stop, it will do so. Ergo, if the expected externality is realized, if the pollution continues, we can infer that it must not have been worth it to pay them to stop, and then it is not indicative of any suboptimality. Only unexpected externalities are market failures because only they preclude the possibility of a Pareto efficient transaction (all of this is assuming no transaction costs).
Jon Murphy
Sep 22 2020 at 9:04am
An externality is defined as a market failure. If there is not one, there is not the other.
Jon Murphy
Sep 21 2020 at 4:51pm
The important thing to remember is this: just because some transaction could exist does not mean it should exist. As Ronald Coase showed us back in 1960, externalities differ in no respect from other transactions.
Mark Z
Sep 22 2020 at 12:58am
This certainly makes case for Pigovian taxes much subtler. It hinges, as I see it, on transaction costs. This may actually be a rare case of a ‘public choice’ argument for rather than against government intervention. Take the case of carbon emissions: the cost is so widely diffuse that it’s analogous to carbon emitters collectively taking a penny from each of us (each of us also sometimes being carbon emitters of course) every day, in the form of damaging the environment. However, the cost, being so diffused, is so small for each party that it isn’t worth it to try to pay individual emitters to emit less carbon. Much like the classic public choice example of a special interest group lobbying to effectively tax $1 from each citizen, it isn’t worth it to show up and vote just to save $1. That’s the case for why this constitutes an opportunity for the state to increase economic efficiency. As long as the price imposes on carbon emission isn’t too much higher than the ideal market rate (in a world without transaction costs) it can at least move the economy closer to the optimum.
Jon Murphy
Sep 22 2020 at 9:03am
You are right that transaction costs being a necessary (though not significant) condition for government intervention is the commonly understood reasoning. But the ubiquitous nature of costs means that, even with externalitites, they cannot in and of themselves contribute to market failure. That is why you have to look beyond the simple story of costs, as Boudreaux and Meiners do.
You are absolutely correct. However, a statement of market failure at its core is a statement of government competency. As Bryan Caplan discussed the other day, public choice gives us reasons to be suspicious of government intervention. If the externality costs us each $1, but the political costs are $1.25 per person to mitigate it, then the case for government falls apart.
In short, the story is not solely about transaction costs but about the costs of government. That’s where the bigger disagreement between Pigou and Coase reside (as Harold Demsetz points out, Pigou did use transaction costs in his discussion of externalitites).
Jon Murphy
Sep 22 2020 at 9:07am
To be clear, I am not disagreeing with what you wrote. It’s spot on. I’m showing it’s even more subtle than you said.
Thomas Hutcheson
Sep 23 2020 at 12:21pm
“Such [external] costs or benefits are, therefore, not only involuntary, but more importantly, unexpected by third parties to the exchange.”
Not necessarily unexpected. The harm caused by the CO2 emitted from oxidizing carbon atoms is not unexpected by anyone. In addition there is the issue of where the incentive to expend resources in developing an “expectation” comes from.
Let’s go with the barber and jackhammer example. Even if both have reasonable expectations about the probability distributions of benefits and costs of barbering and jackhammering that does not mean that there is not a positive sum accommodation of interests. Indeed, I understand the Coase Theorem to imply that with low enough transactions costs the parties can find the optimal accommodation. Expectations are not ALL that matter.
“It therefore does not follow that embracing one analytical point of departure or the other implies the dismissal of or appeal to government intervention as a corrective.”
In my experience, “not necessarily” IS used to dismiss to government intervention as a corrective, at least in the area of net CO2 emissions.
The overbooking problem seems out of place in a discussion of externalities. The airline and passenger are in an (incomplete) contractual relation in a way that the barber and jackhammer operator or fossil fuel oxidizer and Bangladeshi coastal dweller are not.
“Rather, the economist must always approach each analysis of any state of affairs as “nothing but a seething mass of unexploited maladjustments waiting to be corrected” (Kirzner 1979, p. 119), and focus on the constant adjustments that market processes facilitate in an open-ended world of uncertainty.”
This seems perfectly sensible and (approximately) the way most policy-oriented economists do view policy space, or think they view it. What is more problematic is the conclusion that economists should “focus [only] on the constant adjustments that market processes facilitate in an open-ended world of uncertainty” to the exclusion of possible extra-market adjustments.
Robert Schadler
Oct 5 2020 at 4:10pm
Market failure vs government failure. Concepts often overdone.
Humans are all limited as well as imperfect. It should hardly surprise (akin to inexact expectations) that the institutions and processes they create and use are also limited and imperfect.
The use of airplane seat tickets is a fascinating, but perhaps idiosyncratic, case.
More interesting might be to contrast the limitations or imperfections of a market with fixed prices vs a market with auction prices. At the end of the day, a seller of the same good or service who uses one approach will most likely have a different profit than had he used the other approach. Likewise the buyers in a fixed price market would have a different result from those buying the same product in an auction or bargaining market. Is one or the other “better”?
Transaction cost are relevant: an auction or bargaining may well take more time. But “time” is a formal cost if you hire people; and it is an indeterminant “cost” if the seller would otherwise simply be sitting on a chair.
Comments are closed.